12 04 17

Rubin, Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value

Can one find the concept of content of value in this sense in Marx’s work ? We can ans­wer this ques­tion affir­ma­ti­ve­ly. We remem­ber, for example, in Marx’s words, that « exchange-value is a defi­nite social man­ner of expres­sing the amount of labor bes­to­wed upon an object » (C., I, p. 82). It is obvious that labor is here trea­ted as the abs­tract content which can take this or that social form. When Marx, in the well-known let­ter to Kugelmann of July 11, 1868, says that the social divi­sion of labor is mani­fes­ted in the com­mo­di­ty eco­no­my in the form of value, he again treats social­ly allo­ca­ted labor as the content which can take this or that social form. In the second para­graph of the sec­tion on Commodity Fetishism, Marx says direct­ly that « the content of the deter­mi­na­tion of value » can be found not only in the com­mo­di­ty eco­no­my but also in the patriar­chal fami­ly or on the feu­dal estate. Here, too, as we can see, labor is trea­ted as the content which can take various social forms.

However, in Marx’s work one can also find argu­ments in favor of the oppo­site view­point, accor­ding to which we must consi­der abs­tract labor as the content of value. First of all, we find in Marx’s work some sta­te­ments which direct­ly say this, for example the fol­lo­wing : « They (com­mo­di­ties) are rela­ted to abs­tract human labor as to their gene­ral social sub­stance » (Kapital, 1, 1867, p. 28. Italics by I. R.). This sta­te­ment seems to leave no doubt about the fact that abs­tract labor is not only the crea­tor of value, but also the sub­stance and content of value. We reach this same conclu­sion on the basis of metho­do­lo­gi­cal consi­de­ra­tions. Socially equa­li­zed labor acquires the form of abs­tract labor in the com­mo­di­ty eco­no­my, and only from this abs­tract labor fol­lows the neces­si­ty of value as the social form of the pro­duct of labor. From this it fol­lows that the concept of abs­tract labor in our sche­ma direct­ly pre­cedes the concept of value. One might say that this concept of abs­tract labor must be taken as the basis, as the content and sub­stance of value. One can­not for­get that, on the ques­tion of the rela­tion bet­ween content and form, Marx took the stand­point of Hegel, and not of Kant. Kant trea­ted form as some­thing exter­nal in rela­tion to the content, and as some­thing which adheres to the content from the out­side. From the stand­point of Hegel’s phi­lo­so­phy, the content is not in itself some­thing to which form adheres from the out­side. Rather, through its deve­lop­ment, the content itself gives birth to the form which was alrea­dy latent in the content. Form neces­sa­ri­ly grows out of the content itself. This is a basic pre­mise of Hegel’s and Marx’s metho­do­lo­gy, a pre­mise which is oppo­sed to Kant’s metho­do­lo­gy. From this point of view, the form of value neces­sa­ri­ly grows out of the sub­stance of value. Therefore, we must take abs­tract labor in all the varie­ty of its social pro­per­ties cha­rac­te­ris­tic for a com­mo­di­ty eco­no­my, as the sub­stance of value. And, final­ly, if we take abs­tract labor as the content of value, we achieve a signi­fi­cant sim­pli­fi­ca­tion of Marx’s entire sche­ma. In this case, labor as the content of value does not dif­fer from labor which creates value.

,
« Content and form of value » Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value [1928]
,
trad.  Milos Samardfija trad.  Fredy Perlman
, , ,
p. 117–118